Introduction |
|
ix | |
|
|
|
The Analytical Method in Descartes' Geometrie |
|
|
3 | (32) |
|
|
Arcanum Artis Inveniendi: Leibniz and Analysis |
|
|
35 | (12) |
|
|
|
35 | (1) |
|
|
36 | (1) |
|
|
37 | (1) |
|
|
38 | (1) |
|
|
39 | (2) |
|
|
41 | (1) |
|
|
42 | (2) |
|
An Engine for Your Thoughts |
|
|
44 | (3) |
|
The Background to and Early Emergence of Euler's Analysis |
|
|
47 | (32) |
|
|
|
47 | (1) |
|
Analytical Methods in Early Modern Mathematics |
|
|
47 | (16) |
|
|
63 | (10) |
|
|
73 | (6) |
|
Jacob Bernoulli on Analysis, Synthesis, and the Law of Large Numbers |
|
|
79 | (24) |
|
|
|
79 | (2) |
|
Jacob Bernoulli on Analysis and Synthesis |
|
|
81 | (2) |
|
A Priori, A Posteriori, and the Law of Large Numbers |
|
|
83 | (2) |
|
Bernoulli's Proof of the Law of Large Numbers |
|
|
85 | (2) |
|
Cases (casus) and Bernoulli's Conceptions of God and the World |
|
|
87 | (6) |
|
Algebra and the Law of Large Numbers |
|
|
93 | (1) |
|
|
94 | (9) |
|
Mathematical Analysis and Analytical Science |
|
|
103 | (44) |
|
|
|
103 | (5) |
|
The Algebraic Foundation of Mathematical Analysis |
|
|
108 | (20) |
|
Convergence and Continuity as the Trends of the New Analysis |
|
|
128 | (19) |
|
The Analysis of the Synthesis of the Analysis ... Two Moments of a Chiasmus: Viete and Fourier |
|
|
147 | (30) |
|
|
|
147 | (2) |
|
Viete or Analysis Seen as an Appeal for a Constructive Synthesis |
|
|
149 | (5) |
|
Fourier or the Synthesis Appearing as an Analytical Necessity |
|
|
154 | (11) |
|
Fourier's Transform: an Erasing of Synthesis |
|
|
165 | (4) |
|
The Scientific Sufficiency of a Chiasmus |
|
|
169 | (8) |
|
Styles of Argumentation in Late 19th Century Geometry and the Structure of Mathematical Modernity |
|
|
177 | (24) |
|
|
|
177 | (1) |
|
From Synthesis and Analysis to Concrete and Abstract Styles of Mathematical Argumentation |
|
|
178 | (5) |
|
A Philosophical Analysis of Concrete and Abstract Arguments |
|
|
183 | (7) |
|
The Role of Concrete and Abstract Argumentative Styles in Mathematical Modernity |
|
|
190 | (11) |
|
|
|
From Backward Reduction to Configurational Analysis |
|
|
201 | (26) |
|
|
|
201 | (4) |
|
The Directional Interpretation of Analysis: Pappus's Description |
|
|
205 | (2) |
|
The Configurational Interpretation of Analysis: Descartes's Description |
|
|
207 | (1) |
|
|
208 | (9) |
|
The Heuristic Role of Auxiliary Constructions |
|
|
217 | (4) |
|
The Logical Role of Auxiliary Constructions |
|
|
221 | (6) |
|
Analysis, Hermeneutics, Mathematics |
|
|
227 | (16) |
|
|
|
227 | (1) |
|
Greek Analytical Suspension: Hermeneutics and Deliberation |
|
|
227 | (4) |
|
|
231 | (4) |
|
The Identity of the Branch Analysis of Contemporary Mathematics |
|
|
235 | (8) |
|
Science within Reason: Is there a Crisis of the Modern Sciences? |
|
|
243 | (18) |
|
|
|
243 | (1) |
|
Rationality, Intentionality and Everyday Experience |
|
|
244 | (4) |
|
|
248 | (3) |
|
The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction |
|
|
251 | (2) |
|
|
253 | (4) |
|
|
257 | (1) |
|
|
258 | (3) |
|
Mathematics as an Activity and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction |
|
|
261 | (12) |
|
|
|
Intensional and Extensional Theories |
|
|
261 | (1) |
|
Analytical and Synthetical Judgments |
|
|
262 | (6) |
|
|
268 | (1) |
|
Mathematics as an Activity |
|
|
269 | (4) |
|
Mathematical Acts of Reasoning as Synthetic a priori |
|
|
273 | (54) |
|
|
|
273 | (1) |
|
|
273 | (4) |
|
A Provisional Reformulation of Kant's Distinction |
|
|
277 | (6) |
|
Concept, Object and Intuition: the Final Version of Kant's Distinction |
|
|
283 | (10) |
|
|
293 | (2) |
|
Analytic and Synthetic Acts of Reasoning |
|
|
295 | (7) |
|
Naive Formalism and Conceptualism |
|
|
302 | (3) |
|
Madame Bovary as a Pure Object |
|
|
305 | (2) |
|
|
307 | (5) |
|
|
312 | (6) |
|
Concepts of Objects, Concepts of Properties: the Essential Character of Mathematics |
|
|
318 | (3) |
|
|
321 | (6) |
|
Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics from the Perspective of Charles S. Peirce's Philosophy |
|
|
327 | (38) |
|
|
|
327 | (3) |
|
Analysis and Synthesis from Leibniz to Kant |
|
|
330 | (6) |
|
|
336 | (7) |
|
Some Issues where Peirce and Kant differ |
|
|
343 | (10) |
|
The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction according to Peirce is only relative |
|
|
353 | (6) |
|
Pure and Applied Mathematics: Some Examples of Non-Kantian Applications of Mathematics |
|
|
359 | (6) |
|
III. History and Philosophy |
|
|
|
Classical Sources for the Concepts of Analysis and Synthesis |
|
|
365 | (50) |
|
|
|
367 | (2) |
|
|
369 | (1) |
|
|
370 | (8) |
|
Aristotelian Forms of Analysis |
|
|
378 | (5) |
|
Analysis and Synthesis According to Pappus |
|
|
383 | (14) |
|
|
397 | (4) |
|
|
401 | (14) |
Bibliography |
|
415 | (20) |
Index of Names |
|
435 | |