Acknowledgments |
|
ix | |
Introduction |
|
1 | (6) |
|
1 Problems for the Descriptivist Assumption |
|
|
7 | (8) |
|
2 The Attractions of the Normativist Approach |
|
|
15 | (3) |
|
|
18 | (2) |
|
1 The Rise and Fall of Early Non-Descriptive Approaches |
|
|
20 | (32) |
|
1.1 The Pre-History: Challenges for Empiricism |
|
|
21 | (3) |
|
1.2 Conventionalism and Its Motives |
|
|
24 | (3) |
|
1.3 Criticisms of Conventionalism |
|
|
27 | (4) |
|
1.4 Later Non-Descriptivism and the Normative Function of Modal Discourse |
|
|
31 | (5) |
|
1.5 Why the Non-Descriptivist Approach Was Lost |
|
|
36 | (8) |
|
1.6 New Barriers to Modal Non-Descriptivism |
|
|
44 | (4) |
|
1.7 A Non-Descriptivist Revival |
|
|
48 | (3) |
|
1.8 Where Do We Go from Here? |
|
|
51 | (1) |
|
2 The Function of Modal Discourse |
|
|
52 | (25) |
|
2.1 Games, Necessities, and the Advantages of Modal Terminology |
|
|
59 | (4) |
|
2.2 The Function of Metaphysical Modal Terminology |
|
|
63 | (5) |
|
2.3 Uses of Metaphysical Modal Claims |
|
|
68 | (3) |
|
2.4 How Should We Understand the Semantic Rules? |
|
|
71 | (6) |
|
3 The Meaning of Modal Discourse |
|
|
77 | (15) |
|
3.1 The Relation between Function and Use |
|
|
78 | (4) |
|
3.2 The Content of Modal Terms |
|
|
82 | (3) |
|
3.3 Modal Propositions and Modal Truth |
|
|
85 | (3) |
|
3.4 Avoiding the Criticisms of Conventionalism |
|
|
88 | (2) |
|
|
90 | (2) |
|
4 Handling De Re and A Posteriori Modal Claims |
|
|
92 | (21) |
|
4.1 Rules for Names and Natural Kind Terms |
|
|
95 | (10) |
|
|
105 | (3) |
|
4.3 A Posteriori Modal Claims |
|
|
108 | (3) |
|
4.4 The Contingent A Priori |
|
|
111 | (1) |
|
|
112 | (1) |
|
5 Other Objections to Modal Normativism |
|
|
113 | (16) |
|
5.1 Putative Counterexamples |
|
|
114 | (4) |
|
5.1.1 Rules without Necessities? |
|
|
114 | (1) |
|
5.1.2 Necessities without Rules? |
|
|
115 | (1) |
|
5.1.3 Necessary Existents |
|
|
115 | (2) |
|
5.1.4 Modal Demonstratives |
|
|
117 | (1) |
|
|
118 | (6) |
|
5.3 Does It Rely on a Heavyweight Understanding of Logical Necessity? |
|
|
124 | (4) |
|
|
128 | (1) |
|
|
129 | (18) |
|
6.1 Modal Facts and Properties |
|
|
129 | (3) |
|
|
132 | (5) |
|
|
137 | (6) |
|
6.4 Classificatory (and Other Forms of) Conventionalism |
|
|
143 | (4) |
|
7 Epistemological Advantages |
|
|
147 | (38) |
|
7.1 The Integration Challenge |
|
|
150 | (7) |
|
7.2 The Reliability Challenge |
|
|
157 | (4) |
|
7.3 Meeting the Integration Challenge |
|
|
161 | (4) |
|
7.4 Meeting the Reliability Challenge |
|
|
165 | (5) |
|
7.5 Does the Challenge Arise Again? |
|
|
170 | (5) |
|
7.6 The Unexplained Coincidence Problem |
|
|
175 | (7) |
|
|
182 | (3) |
|
8 Methodological Advantages |
|
|
185 | (24) |
|
8.1 Justifying the Use of Intuition in Metaphysical Modal Debates |
|
|
187 | (2) |
|
8.2 A Defense of the Relevance of Traditional Methods |
|
|
189 | (2) |
|
8.3 Resolving Internal Metaphysical Modal Disputes |
|
|
191 | (5) |
|
8.4 Objections to Conceptual Analysis |
|
|
196 | (2) |
|
8.5 Limits to Detail and Precision |
|
|
198 | (2) |
|
8.6 Understanding External Metaphysical Modal Disputes |
|
|
200 | (6) |
|
|
206 | (3) |
Conclusion |
|
209 | (8) |
Bibliography |
|
217 | (12) |
Index |
|
229 | |